Empirical Evaluation of Theories of Peasantry

Leopold Pospíšil

Like other social sciences, anthropology has theorized about peasantry and

its basic concepts in many ways, most of which contradict each other. Shanin

viewed them as fitting four major categories. First, the European authors have

presented peasantry as an earlier cultural tradition which lags behind modern

socio-economic development. For Marx, peasantry meant a class of producers

formerly exploited by elite of the pre-capitalist society, which presently

represents a leftover from the preceding evolutionary societal stage (1975: 3).

Authors of the third category, like Chayanov, regarded peasantry as a special

type of mode of production. Finally, DurkHeim and his anthropological followers

like Kroeber claimed peasantry to be a structural component of civilization,

in Kroeber’s terms, a “part society” (1948: 284).

Of the above theories, especially the Marxist concept has to be rejected on

empirical grounds. If one views exploitation as payment of the rent and of the

various fees extracted from peasantry, then are not we all in a sense exploited

by having to pay sometimes very onerous taxes imposed upon us by the lawyers

and politicians? Furthermore, in various times and places, not all peasantry

would fit the Marxist classification. In different times and places, peasants of

Europe and Asia were not subject to payment of the rent or being some sort

of underdogs. Indeed, sometimes they shared in the power of the State (e.g.

in Czechoslovakia, Poland, Bulgaria, Switzerland, and even in Communist

China). In Austria, a country in which I have conducted long-term research,

Austrian peasantry, the Bauern, have for a long time enjoyed the highest social

status (as also Khera points out; 1972: 352). In my native Czechoslovakia the

largest “agrarian party” ruled the country, in a coalition, for its democratic

duration of twenty years (1918-1938). As a consequence of the supposed idea

that all peasants are exploited underlings, Marxists and also the subscribers to

the concept of the “peasant mode of production” hold that the peasants practice

subsistence economy, that they produce only for feeding their family and

pay the required rent or taxes (see Cole and Wolf 1914: 87, 140, 152; Roseburry

1976: esp. 51). But it had been the peasant production which provided the surplus

which paid for the cities and castles and which fed the industrial revolution

(Potter 1967a: 380). Roseburry admits that some peasants themselves became

capitalists exploiting the poorer peasants (1976, esp. 50-51). In the definition of

surplus, Marxists and other authors leave out investments made by peasants on

their farm and business activities, such as building farmhouses, payments to

co-heirs in areas of impartible inheritance, buying equipment and machinery,

providing irrigation and drainage, creating new arable land, building of roads

and bridges, buying superior breeding stock, etc. Thus capital is not limited to

purchasing labor only, as Wolf claims (Worsley 1984: 17).

Some theories seem to be even more detached from reality. In order to

keep logical with their tenets that, in their production, the aim of the peasants

is basically satisfaction of their households’ needs, they claim that they use little

money in their subsistence economy (Wolf 1955: 454; Shanin 1975a: 15).

Some authors go as far as to view peasants living in a non-money economy.

With the advent of money, they supposedly slowly transformed their peasant

type of production into an enterprise of a capitalist nature (Shanim 1975a:

16). Even worse, the peasants are often depicted as being resigned to their fate

and passive when faced with problems of survival choices. Poverty and struggle

for survival are supposedly regarded as inevitable, and any innovation is

primarily viewed as pathological in nature (Cole and Wolf 1974: 152; Ortiz

1975: 330-331). These absurd assertions have been challenged by many. Herring

shows that peasants who faced great adversity as exploited sharecroppers

were challenged rather than resigned to their fate, and produced more than

owner-

operators (1984: 136). Indeed, Ortiz categorically states that peasants

not only operate in a money economy, but also that their decisions can “easily

be explained in terms of the state of the market, that peasant behavior does

not seem to be so different from Western producers” (1975: 331). David Greenwood

agrees that every peasant feeds his family but also runs an enterprise,

thus actually being a manager and entrepreneur (in Durrenberger 1980: 134).

Similarly Thorner claims that peasants produce for exchange (in Ortiz 1975:

323) and Diaz demonstrates that “the peasant village is not economically selfsufficient,

depending upon a wide network of personas to whom peasants

sell their surplus handicrafts and produce, and from whom they purchase the

goods that they themselves do not produce” (Potter et al. 1967: 165; see also

Wilk 1991: 5). Indeed, even some Marxists claim that there is no special peas194

ant mode of production (Tannenbaum 1984a: 31). Foster shows that the prices

peasants charge are determined by international forces and local monopolists

(Potter et al. 1967a: 9). Even most of the peasants of Thailand produce beyond

subsistence level, as Tannenbaum shows (1984: 938).

Data from Obernberg Valley, a village which I have subjected to long-term

research, studying it since 1962 (when I stayed for a whole year), and returning

every year since (spending over seven years there, when counted together),

contradict all the above definitions of peasantry. They are more in line with the

above-mentioned critiques of Ortiz, Diaz, and Foster. My quantitative research

discloses that the peasants of Obernberg lived in a money economy and produced

a surplus not only to pay the fees and taxes extracted by the past nobles

and later the state, but also for investment and profit. It is not true that peasants

have a static technology (see also Nettig 1981: xiii), as shown by my data

on the constant technological modernization of Obernberg. Peasants accepted

proven technological inventions (scythe, water power, wind power, electricity,

cable hay lifts, hay slides), and a whole array of modem power tools and

machinery. Indeed they accepted new crops (potatoes, tomatoes, and a variety

of vegetables). They have made maximization of income their basic strategy,

as Gamst concurs (1974: 34). This aptitude for market for which one does not

have to be literate and have legal codes as Gamst suggests (1974:34) and profit

motivation are easily discerned in my quantitative data of the year 1967, when

non-farm activity provided a full 47.14 % of income for Obernberg’s 50 farms.

Only during political and national crises, when the market collapsed, did they

return to subsistence strategy. Unlike specialized farms and especially the various

kolkhozes, producers associations, and latifundia of rich individuals, the

peasants showed great economic flexibility (also Wiber 1985: 437).

As Wolf aptly states, the peasants’ control of land enables them to retreat

into subsistence and “insulating adaptation” when need demands (Cole and

Wolf 1974: 30). Because of this flexibility and unification of management and

labor, the peasant family farm has a far greater capacity for survival than the

commercial and state farms. Soviet collectivization, for example, with its system

of kolkhozes and state farms, transformed the once surplus-producing

Ukraine (“the old breadbasket of Europe”) and the whole Soviet State into

a food importing country. In times of crisis, peasant family production usually

subsidizes the urban population (Jones 1984: 161). In present and past times

of prosperity, Obernberg’s diversified agriculture, with its field of grain and

potatoes, disappeared and gave way to areas of grassland which provide fodder

for cattle, the merchandise for market-oriented production. Such flexibility is

hardly possible on a large commercial or state-owned farm.

A widespread theoretical ethnographic tradition comes from European

ethnologists. There the peasants are viewed as representatives of an outdated

tradition, or simply as survivors because of supposed inertia typical of peasant

societies (Sharin 1975b: 148; also Foster 1967a: 9; Diaz 1967: 50). The traditionalist

and conformist theory originated from the supposed peasants’ fear of

the outside world. As Ortiz shows, this “traditionalism” of peasants stems from

past experience when holding to the old method of production avoided risks

with untested new urban ideas and minimized losses and starvation (1975:

334). From my own experience, I can claim that holding to the old ways is

sometimes reinforced by failures of urban “scientific advisors.” Was it so clever

that in the USA and, for example, in Czechoslovakia, the abandonment of traditional

crop rotation and reliance on artificial chemical fertilizers ruined the

balanced ecology, rendered the groundwater undrinkable, and choked the fish

streams and lakes with algae? Moreover, the new urban reliance on fertilizers

and modem cultivation techniques produce cash outlays and involve long-term

costs that a farmer can hardly afford. In the village of Vojnice (Czechoslovakia),

where I farmed for five years (1942-1946), wasting the available manure and

straw, in a new Soviet-styled kolkhoz, resulted in a mountain of a 40-year accumulation

of manure surrounded by a smelly lake of liquid animal excreta and

another mountain of rotting straw, and failed to produce the promised increase

in production and income (see also Ortiz 1975: 334). While working on my

research among the Hopi Indians of Arizona, I heard a very relevant story. An

expert from Washington came to teach the Indians how to grow corn. With his

tractor he plowed a field in the nearby arroyo (dried-out river bed) and planted

corn, while his Hopi neighbors used their old digging sticks and dispensed with

the plowing. Soon the Hopi Indian field was green from growing corn, while

that of the “urban expert” was bare. By plowing, the famous agronomist had

destroyed the soil capillarity and rendered his field barren. No wonder that,

after few of such experiments, the peasants view new inventions with caution

and very slowly accept only those that have demonstrably proved to be successful.

Similar critique is expressed by Minz (1973) and Netting (1981: 228).

Peasantry develops only in a civilization. A civilization does not have to

have writing and written literature, as the Inca civilization demonstrates. A civilization

is defined by the existence of a city, which other forms of societies do

not possess. A city, in turn, is a community which, irrespective of its size, is

economically not self-sufficient, but depends for food on the Hinterland, an area

dotted with villages. In exchange, it provides defense, services of social, commercial,

religious, political and educational nature, and products of craftsmen

or industry. Thus peasants of the villages are structurally bound to the city and

necessarily participate in the monetary and market economy. Consequently,

the claim that the peasants are isolated, not profit-oriented and practice subsistence

economy is obviously incorrect (also see Foster 1967: 5; Redfield 1953:

40; Kroeber 1948: 284, Diaz 1967: 51). The city functions not only as a political

partner, an outlet for the peasants’ produce, and the source of material goods,

inventions, and services, but also as the source of peasants’ dependence and

sometimes subjugation and political domination. As a consequence, a proper

study of peasantry requires of necessity discussion of the history, economy,

laws, and associational structure of the associated province and the state as

they relate to the village life (also claimed by Wolf 1956: 1066).

The contact between the city and its Hinterland has been culturally

expressed by some authors as a duality of the Great and Little Tradition. The

great tradition of the city is supposed to contain the educational elite which,

by its advanced knowledge, dominates the political and economic life of the

rural population. Accordingly, the city is portrayed as to provide the important

innovations, architects who built the monumental structures, and the painters,

sculptors and literary people who produce the advanced academic achievements

and art. The countryside, we are told, contains only a simplified version of the

elaborate city’s “Great Tradition” (Redfield in Foster 1967: 6). In the religious

sphere, Gamst goes to the extreme in claming that the city provides priests and

nuns, and that the backward countryside peasants function only as spectators,

possessing only superstitions as their own religious product. Indeed Gamst

generalizes that peasants are illiterate and their illiteracy reaffirms more absolutely

the contrasts between city dwellers and peasants (1974: 14). Because of

this illiteracy and traditionalism, the peasants are supposed to need an agent to

mediate between them and the city to interpret “The Great Tradition’s cultural

achievements and inventions” (Potter et al. 1967b: 9).

All these simply fantastic generalizations are readily contracted by cultural

achievements of peasantry in Europe and Asia, and, of course, by my findings

in Obernberg (Tirol, Austria). The Obernberg peasants, although having

some of their own legends and superstitions, participate fully in the Roman

Catholic Church activity. Peasant illiteracy, if applied to Europe, is simply nonsense.

Obernberg produced several well-educated priests and even a university

professor and a doctor of veterinary medicine. Many of the Obernberg farmers

graduated not only from European high school, but also from college or university.

To explain the folly of the above-mentioned theories, one has to realize

that not only did the authors mentioned study only the Latin American (mostly

Mexican) situation, but they also appear to be ignorant of the peasantry of the

rest of the world. In Europe and Obernberg, the rural people have their own

subculture in their own right, with their own dialect and written literature,

songs, poetry, original architecture, style of furniture, food recipes, and folk

costumes. None of these are some sort of derivations from their neighboring

city culture. The small valley of Obernberg, up to 1967 partially isolated by

a precipitous and dangerous road to the outer world, prides itself on its own

dialect, local legends, an Olympic gold medalist in skiing, two highly literate

and knowledgeable “Heimatforscher” (Andreas Saxer and Herman Hilber, students

of the local folklore and history).

Peasantry had been viewed by many anthropologists as a category characterized

by several attributes. The most widespread one requires that the peasants

be farmers to qualify as members of this category (Wolf 1966; Handlin

1981: 466; Ortiz et al. 1967: 6; Shanin 1975a: 15). True enough, most peasants

are engaged in farming, but the villages also contain craftsmen who share their

life with other farming village co-residents. One has to view peasantry not as

a category but as a subculture which includes the farming and non-farming

population. In Obernberg, for example, the district of Eben housed laborers

with little land to farm and, in the district of Aue, specialized craftsmen such as

cobblers, tailors, basket makers, carpenters, masons, and weavers conducted

their business. Besides, the claim that peasants, unlike modern farmers, do not

cultivate cash crops is contradicted by the history of Obernberg and also most

of Central Europe, where cash crops have been produced by peasants since the

Middle Ages. Again, peasantry is a subculture or sub-society tied structurally

to the city, and not a category.

Equally false is the claim that peasants have simple technology, resisting

change coming from outside. The truth is that they accepted new technology as

soon as it was proven to be successful and efficient. Thus Obernberg displayed

modem machinery, electrification and architecture. However, they are still

reluctant to use extensively insecticide and herbicides that poison the water

and exterminate useful birds and animals. Pests (mice, moles, harmful insects,

squirrels, and rabbits) are still mostly controlled by predatory insects (wasps,

hornets, lady bugs, praying mantises, etc.), singing birds, hawks, owls, ferrets

and foxes. The old plow, which brings up the low layers of fertile soil filled with

nutrients from cow manure, is still in full use rather than the modem cultivator

which just churns up the top soil, leaving the unused nutrients of the lower

level unused and wasted.

Peasantry theorizing has not left out the personality of the rural population.

Unfortunately the concept of the personality of peasants and the various

theories are not clearly stated, and the terms used remained not well defined

(see also Ortiz 1975: 327). Furthermore, the authors’ theories disclose a strange

naiveté mainly due to studying an individual’s statement and attitudes rather

than comparing their interpretations with hard economic realities. The result is

that Netting’s and my empirical findings can hardly be compared with the typical

peasant personality of anthropological literature (Pospisil 1995: 14; Netting

1981: 227). The peasant characteristics that are claimed may not even be

shared by all the individuals studied (Diaz 1975: 327) and the ideal described is

usually viewed as an equivalent to reality (Ortiz 1975: 333). So, for example, the

claim that equality is the overriding value of the peasants is not brought out by

empirical reality. My Obernberg findings, and also those of Ortiz, show that to

assert that peasants supposedly form a uniform, homogeneous society is simply

an illusion. My Obernberg people range from conservatives to progressives,

which was clearly demonstrated by their decision-making concerning their use

of machines, selection of crops, and the acceptance or rejection of new cultivation

techniques, especially those involving the use of chemical fertilizers and

pesticides. These findings show the impossibility of putting a categorical label

of “progressive” or “conservative” on all the Obernberg farmers.

Another dubious generalization states that peasants have an implicit, covert

“image of limited good” (Foster 1967: 296). They are supposed to believe

that desired things in life exist in limited quantity that cannot be increased.

Therefore this limited good should be more equally distributed and not hoarded

by a few individuals. From this, therefore, stems their hostility toward wealth.

Having been a European farmer for five years, and having studied Obernberg

peasants since 1962 (a total of seven years of research), my interpretation of

this hostility views it as simple envy. In this respect, there is no difference

between the urban and rural populations in Europe. In comparison, the culture

of the United States is conspicuous for a relative lack of envy. So it may be

that Americans who study peasants abroad, while relatively ignorant of their

urban compatriots, view this envy as a special mark of peasantry. An anecdote

expresses the problem of envy difference between American and European cultures

quite well. In Europe, Franz prays to God, complaining that his neighbor

has a nice pig. God appears and asks Franz, “Do you wish a pig like your

neighbor’s?” “No, God,” replies Franz, “I wish my neighbor’s pig were dead.”

In a similar situation in the United States, Frank, a counterpart of Franzi, certainly

has a different wish: “No, God, I would like to have ten pigs like his.”

The joke reveals the pure envy of a European peasant rather than any feeling

of a “limited good.” There is another controversy over the conception of

a peasant personality. While in his study of the Tepoztlan community of Mexico,

Redfield claims that the peasants displayed idyllic behavior, Oscar Lewis,

who restudied the same community, found the people there to be suspicious,

individualistic, envious, and uncooperative (Redfield 1930; Lewis 1960). My

research in Obernberg and in the Czech village of Vojnice, where I farmed for

five years, suggests that both of the authors were, in a sense, right. In Europe

as in Mexico, and unlike in the USA, peasants as well as urbanites have a double

standard of behavior. They classify people with whom they interact into two

categories: the proximate, including relatives, friends and underlings, and the

distant category of acquaintances, strangers, superiors and enemies. Members

of the two categories are addressed by different pronouns (e.g. du and Sie in

German, tu and vous in French, tu and usted in Spanish, etc.). Radically different

patterns of behavior are applied to these. Members of the distant category

are suspect; one is reserved and uncooperative toward them, possibly even hostile.

With “proximate” people, one tends to be helpful, trusting, open and unreserved

in one’s behavior. These patterns are not particular to peasantry, but are

applied in European and Mexican societies to all their members. During my

first two years of stay in Obernberg, the people were suspicious and mistrusting

of me, but afterwards I was reclassified as “proximate” and many of them

opened their lives to me, disclosed their financial status (debits and credits in

their bank accounts). Would an American so openly show me his/her debts,

credits and other financial documents?

This dichotomy in Europe does not mean that there would not be hostilities

between two particular families in Obernberg. Indeed, while in the Obernberg

districts of Aussertal, Innertal, and Leite, the interfamily grievances were

inherited and perpetuated, in the districts of Gereit and Eben the animosities

were open, violent, but short-lived.

In the seventies, the work of Chayanov became popular with the theoreticians

of the West. The heart of the Chayanov’s theory is the on-farm equilibrium,

the point where additional effort and production cease. It is determined by

the balance between the family needs of the Russian farmer and the supposed

drudgery of labor expended to meet these needs. The needs and the drudgery

of expended work are subtle and hard to determine. They form two curves and,

at their intersection, the labor of the Russian peasant studied is supposed to

cease. Since additional factors determine this utility (needs of the family) and

drudgery of expended work, it is difficult to be exactly identified; Sahlins used

the easily identifiable ratio of consumers and number of the productive workers

of the family and correlated this with the household production. Thus, to

Sahlins, the intensity of a given household’s production varies inversely with

the relative working capacity of the domestic unit. In other words, Sahlins

assumes that all peasants of the world tend to work only to supply the needs

of their families and are not motivated by profit (Sahlins in Tennenbaum 1984:

927). Aside from the fact that Chayanov also worked with other factors and not

only with the two simple ones used by Sahlins, Sahlins and followers of Chayanov

failed to understand the data Chayanov worked with. His source of facts

came from the Soviet Union of the twenties, from the apartitional communes

whose peasants, dominated by the Communist administration, were assigned

and reassigned amounts of lands with regard to the changing size of their families.

These communes were, of course, an artificial construct of the Communist

revolutionaries and thus had little to do with actual peasantry. Since, in

my Obernberg and in most other peasant communities, one’s landholdings

cannot be enlarged or diminished at will, Chayanov’s findings, while very good

for understanding the early Soviet agrarian era, are irrelevant to the rest of the

world’s peasantry.

As in other social studies, theories of peasantry have not escaped the

influence of Marxism. It became assumed, without any empirical evidence, of

course, that originally peasant villages had held and used all their land communally

(Handlin 1981: 659). The Marxist-influenced authors saw a survival

of the supposed old-time Communism in the contemporary Alpine institution

of Almen, an association holding pasture land in a community. According to

them, Almen represent communes where every farm of the valley is entitled to

pasture its cattle (Cole and Wolf 1974: 99). Unfortunately, Almen are not communes,

but are private corporations in which the farmers have secured rights

to pasture individual heads of cattle, either through long-time use (logaeva consuetude,

usu capio) or through purchase with subsequent incorporation. As

a consequence, in Obernberg only 60 residents and four non-residents have

pasture rights, while two Obernberg farms have no rights, and 13 farmers

acquired pasture rights in Almen of the neighboring community of Gries. There

is little relation between the size of a farm and its number of head of cattle entitled

to use the pasture in Obernberg’s ten Almen. In conclusion, Almen are

certainly not communes, but corporations whose legal rights and duties form

a fictive legal personality separate from those of its members. They are not economically

wasteful and irrational as Friedl claims (1974: 52-55). My quantitative

analysis, which Friedl lacks, shows just the opposite. Neither the putative

ancient collectivism of Marxism nor the forced collectivization of the Soviet

Union of the twentieth century shows any supposed human appeal. Indeed the

Soviet Union under Stalin’s rule had to “liquidate” (under Khrushchev’s direction)

three million peasants in the Ukraine alone.

Another Marxian dogma of an evolutionary stage of an “egalitarian society”

has proven to be a myth, not only among the peasants but also in studied

tribal societies (Netting 1981: 228-229; Wilk 1991: 5; Lewis 1981: 61; Pospisil

1963 and 1995). The population of Obernberg ranged from very poor peasants

to rather well-to-do elite, the former concentrated in the district of Eben, and

the latter in the Ausserthal district.

Leopold Pospíši l, legal anthropologist, professor emeritus of anthropology

and curator emeritus of the Peabody Museum at Yale University. He studied law

at Charles University in Prague, sociology and philosophy at Willamette University

in Oregon and anthropology at the University of Oregon and Yale University. He

delved into the cultures of the Nunamuit Eskimos in Alaska, the Hopi Indians in Arizona

and the Kapauku in New Guinea, and common law among Tyrolean peasants

(in the Obernberg valley, not far from Brenner). He is the author of circa 20 books,

e.g., Kapauku Papuans and their Law (1958), Kapauku Papuan Economy (1963),

Anthropology of Law: A comparative theory (1971), The Ethnology of Law (1997) –

and has lectured in more than 50 universities around the world. He took part in the

anti-Nazi resistance. On March 13, 1948, he left Czechoslovakia. The Czechoslovak

authorities condemned him three times in his absence.

Bibliography

Cole, John W. and Eric R. Wolf. 1974. The Hidden Frontier: Ecology and Ethnicity in an

Alpine Valley. New York and London: Academic Press.

Diaz, May. 1967. “Introduction: Economic Relations in Peasant Society.” Pp. 50-66 in

Potter, Jack M. et al. (eds.): Peasant Society A Reader. Boston: Little, Brown and

Company.

Durrenberger, E. Paul. 1980. “Chayanov’s Economic Analysis in Anthropology.”

Journal of Anthropological Research 36, 1980, 2: 133-148.

Foster, George M. 1967a. “Introduction: What is a Peasant.” Pp. 2-14 in Potter, Jack M.

et al. (eds.): Peasant Society. A Reader. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

Foster, George M. 1967b. “Introduction: Peasant Character and Personality.” Pp.

296-299 in Potter, Jack M. et al. (eds.): Peasant Society. A Reader. Boston: Little,

Brown and Company.

Friedl, John. 1974. Kippel: A Changing Village in the Alps. (Case Studies in Cultural

Anthropology: George and Louise Spindler, eds.). New York: Holt, Rinehart and

Winston, Inc.

Gamst, Frederick C. 1974. Peasants in Complex Society. (Basic Anthropology Units;

George and Louise Spindler, eds.) New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc.

Handlin, Oscar E. 1981. “25 Peasant Origins.” Pp. 456-478 in Dalton, George (ed.):

Tribal and Peasant Economics. Readings in Economic Anthropology. Austin:

University of Texas Press.

Herring, Ronald J. 1984. “Chayanovian versus Neoclassical Perspectives on Land

Tenure and Productivity Interactions.” Pp. 133-149 in Durrenberger, E. Paul (ed.):

Chayanov, Peasants, and Economic Anthropology. Orlando: Academic Press.

Jones, Jeffrey R. 1984. “Chayanov in Bolivia. Changes in Potato Productivity among

Cochabamba Peasants.” Pp. 151-166 in Durrenberger, E. Paul (ed.): Chayanov,

Peasants, and Economic Anthropology. Orlando: Academic Press.

Kroeber, Alfred L. 1948. Anthropology. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

Lewis, Oscar. 1960. Tepoztlan: Village of Mexico. (Case Studies in Cultural

Anthropology). New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Marx, Karl. 1975. “Peasantry as a Class.” Pp. 229-237 in Shanin, Theodor (ed.):

Peasants and Peasant Societies. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books Ltd.

Mintz, Sidney W. 1973. “A Note on Definition of Peasantries.” Journal of Peasant

Studies 1, 1973: 91-106.

Netting, Robert McC. 1981. Balancing on an Alp. Ecological Change and Continuity in

a Swiss Mountain Community. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ortiz, Sutti. 1975. “Reflections on the Concept of ‘Peasant Culture’ and ‘Peasant

Cognitive Systems.’” Pp. 322-336 in Shanin, Theodor (ed.): Peasants and Peasant

Societies. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books Ltd.

Pospisil, Leopold. 1963. Kapauku Papuan Economy. (Yale University Publications

in Anthropology No. 67) New Haven: Department of Anthropology, Yale

University.

Pospisil, Leopold. 1995. Obernberg: A Quantitative Analysis of a Peasant Tirolean

Economy. New Haven: Connecticut Academy of Arts Sciences.

Pospisil, Leopold. 1971. Anthropology of Law. New York: Harper and Row.

Potter, Jack M. 1967. “Introduction: Peasants in the Modern World.” Pp. 378-383 in

Potter, Jack M. et al. (eds.): Peasant Society. A Reader. Boston: Little, Brown and

Company.

Redfield, Robert. 1953. The Primitive World and its Transformations. Ithaca: Cornell

University Press.

Shanin, Theodor (ed.). 1975a. Peasants and Peasant Societies. Harmondsworth:

Penguin Books Ltd.

Shanin, Theodor. 1975b. “Introduction.” Pp. 11-19 in Peasants and Peasant Societies.

Harmondsworth: Penguin Books Ltd.

Tannenbaum, Nicola. 1984a. “Chayanov and Economic Anthropology.” Pp. 27-38 in

Durrenberger, E. Paul (ed.): Chayanov, Peasants, and Economic Anthropology.

Orlando: Academic Press.

Tannenbaum, Nicola. 1984b. “The Misuse of Chayanov: Chayanov’s Rule and

Empiricist Bias in Anthropology.” American Anthropologist 86, 1984, 4: 927-942.

Thorner, Daniel. 1975. “Peasant Economy as a Category in Economic History.” Pp. 387-

400 in Shanin, Theodor (ed.): Peasants and Peasant Societies. Harmondsworth:

Penguin Books Ltd.

Wiber, Malanie G. 1985. “Dynamics of the Peasant Household Economy: Labor

Recruitment and Allocation in an Upland Philippine Community.” Journal

ofAnthropological Research 41, 1985, 4: 427-441.

Wilk, Richard. 1991. “The Household in Anthropology: Panacea or Problem?” Reviews

in Anthropology 20, 1991: l-12.

Wolf, Eric R. 1966. Peasants. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

Worsley, Peter. 1984. “A Landmark in Anthropology: A Review of Eric Wolf’s ‘Europe

and the People without History.’” American Ethnologist 11, 1984, 1: 170-175.


Leopold Pospíšil


Poslední změna: 25. červenec 2018 11:17 
Sdílet na: Facebook Sdílet na: Twitter
Sdílet na:  
Vydavatel

Fakulta humanitních studií Univerzity Karlovy


Kontakty

Časopis "Lidé města"

Fakulta humanitních studií Univerzity Karlovy

Pátkova 2137/5

182 00 Praha 8 - Libeň


e-mail:



Jak k nám